Melissus

Translation Fundraiser

Our vision: Free history education for everyone in the world, in every language. That's a lofty goal indeed, but that won't stop us from working towards it. To get there we need to translate... a lot! Please donate today and help us make a truly global impact. Thank you very much!
$1493 / $3000

Definition

Daniel Costa
by
published on 24 March 2021
Send to Google Classroom:
X
Melissus in the Nuremberg Chronicle (by Singinglemon, Public Domain)
Melissus in the Nuremberg Chronicle
Singinglemon (Public Domain)

Melissus of Samos (5th century BCE) was a Greek philosopher from the island of Samos near the modern-day coast of Turkey. He advocated the philosophical doctrine known as monism, suggesting that reality is single and unchanging. While very little is known about Melissus, he took part in a major battle in 441 BCE and penned one philosophical work called On Nature or On What Is, echoing the naturalistic and monistic stance that pervaded earlier philosophers' output. Due to his views, he is often considered a member of the so-called Eleatic school of Greek philosophy. As James Warren asserts, the fact that Parmenides’ ideas reached the opposite end of the Greek world underlines the circulation of ideas that pervaded the Mediterranean in that historical period.

The Eleatics

The Eleatic school challenged a reliance on the senses as a path to truth, trusting logic instead.

The term Eleatic school of philosophy is used nowadays to refer to the thoughts of philosophers from modern-day Velia in southern Italy, namely Parmenides (l. c. 485 BCE) and Zeno of Elea (l. c. 465 BCE). They challenged a reliance on the senses as a path to truth, trusting logic instead. Parmenides wrote the poem On Nature, where he describes his visit to a goddess who shows him the Way of Truth and the Way of Opinion. The former is grounded in reality and is eternal, motionless, and changeless, while the latter ought to be avoided as it is based on the senses. Similarly, Zeno wrote several paradoxes, such as the well-known Achilles and the Tortoise, to prove that motion is impossible. The school exerted a significant influence on the thought of Athenian philosopher Plato (428/427 - 348/347 BCE) and his theory of forms, which distinguished between the world of the senses and the world of ideas, or forms.

Remove Ads

Advertisement

Historical Background

At the time, Samos belonged to the symmachei (alliance), nowadays referred to as the Delian League, led by Athens in response to Persian invasions. According to Plutarch, Melissus was the son of Ithagenes, a philosopher in command on the island of Samos. Like Parmenides, Melissus was politically active and fought as an admiral against the Athenians in 441 BCE, which is the only reliable date we have for the Samian philosopher. When Athens declared war against the island, Melissus reportedly prompted his fellow islanders to counterattack, despite their relative inexperience and reduced number of ships. They won, seizing war supplies and gaining control of the sea. Eventually, however, Athens triumphed and overtook the island.

Philosophy

Eternity & Infinity

According to the 6th-century CE Neoplatonist philosopher Simplicius, Melissus composed only one work. As opposed to Parmenides, he wrote in an archaic yet clear, direct manner and in Ionic prose rather than in poetic form. This has led scholars to question whether Parmenides considered 'what is' everlasting or timeless. Melissus, on the other hand, clearly argued that 'what is' must have everlasting existence, since nothing can come out of nothing, as opposed to what our misleading perceptions may suggest. To support his views, he developed the following argument:

Remove Ads

Advertisement

Whatever existed always existed and always will exist. For if it came into being, then necessarily before coming into being it was nothing. Now if it was nothing it will in no way have come to be anything from being nothing. (Fragment B1)

In a similar vein, while doubts persist regarding Parmenides’ approach to the size of 'what is', Melissus clearly suggests that it is spatially infinite in extent, from which he infers that there is only one. If there were more than one, there would be boundaries, so it is not enough for 'what is' to be boundless in at least one direction. It must be absolutely boundless. While in Parmenides, the limits and bonds underlined the stability and completeness of 'what is', preventing it from losing anything, in Melissus, it is the unlimited, or apeiron that prevents change.

Bust of Parmenides
Bust of Parmenides
BjörnF (CC BY-SA)

Motion & Void

Melissus also argues against motion and the void. He states that what is empty is nothing and is thus 'what is not'. As a result, 'what is' cannot move and is therefore full, as it has nowhere to yield to. If we compare this to a bottle, for instance, it goes without saying that we can only fill it if it is empty. Similarly, we can only empty it if it is full. Melissus does not suggest, however, that it can be half full or half empty, since he considers the existence of only one thing, and it is either full or not full, he claims, since if it yields at all it is not full anymore. In doing so, Melissus underlines the impossibility of both internal change and motion per se, since if it is full it cannot move. In fact, he claims that density and rarity cannot exist in 'what is' and is, as a result, incorporeal:

Love History?

Sign up for our free weekly email newsletter!

It could not be dense and rare. For it is not possible that the rare should be full, like the dense: the rare thereby at once becomes emptier than the dense. (Fragment 7)

Changeless Reality

Nothing is stronger than truth, Melissus claims, & such superficial changes prevent us from seeing it correctly.

Melissus echoes Parmenides by objecting to a pluralistic view of reality essentially based on perception. He emphasises the inconsistency inherent in the changes between opposites such as hot and cold, hard and soft, and life and death. He also alludes to eternal forms and powers, which seemingly convey the omnipresence of change. Nothing is stronger than truth, he claims, and such superficial changes prevent us from seeing it correctly. He, therefore, believes that should plurality exist, each and everything must be like 'what is', which would, in his view, be inconsistent. In other words, on what grounds would one object be small and another one big? Why would one be soft and another one hard?

Reactions to Melissus

On some accounts, his thoughts eventually paved the way for the development of atomism in the 5th century BCE, advocated by Leucippus and Democritus. They would introduce a very small, indivisible, changeless, and eternal 'what is', the essence of all things, which they called 'atom', a term that would become the cornerstone of modern science. Others, however, suggest that Melissus' contention regarding the impossibility of void can be seen as a response to the atomists, rather than a precursor. Melissus is also mentioned in the Hippocratic On the Nature of the Human Being, in response to the apparently incoherent theories of natural philosophers who sought different first causes of the nature of things.

Remove Ads

Advertisement

Despite the quality of his arguments, in De Generatione et Corruptione, Aristotle criticizes philosophers who defy the evidence provided by the senses. Aristotle attacks Melissus' defence of spatial infinity, which he considered based on faulty logic and a false premise. Melissus is also mentioned by Dante Alighieri (1265-1321) in his Divine Comedy as fulfilling the characteristics of what a philosopher should not be like. On the whole, however, the clarity of his arguments have shed a light on the nature of the Eleatic response to pluralistic views of existence, thereby playing an important role in the emergence of metaphysics and ontology.

Did you like this definition?
Editorial Review This article has been reviewed for accuracy, reliability and adherence to academic standards prior to publication.
Remove Ads

Advertisement

Translations

We want people all over the world to learn about history. Help us and translate this definition into another language!

About the Author

Daniel Costa
An educator and writer, Daniel Costa has studied Philosophy and Music at BA-level and History and language teaching at MA-level. Born in London to an Italian-Portuguese family, he has also lived in Greece, Brazil, Spain, Croatia and Switzerland.

Support Our
Non-Profit Organization

World History Encyclopedia is a non-profit organization. For only $5 per month you can become a member and support our mission to engage people with cultural heritage and to improve history education worldwide.

Become a Member  

Recommended Books

  • Lectures de Mélissos (Studia Praesocratica) (French Edition)
    Written by Brémond, Mathilde, published by De Gruyter (2017)
    $154.99
  • A Companion to Ancient Philosophy (Rereading Ancient Philosophy)
    Written by Kirkland, Sean D & Sanday, Eric & Russon, John & Hyland, Drew & Hopkins, Phil & Gonzalez, Francisco & Stocking, Damian & Baracchi, Claudia & Brogan, Walter & Harvey, George & Oele, Marjolein & Aygün, Ömer & Recco, Greg & McCumber, John & Rabinoff, Eve & Fagan, Patricia & Massie, Pascal & Zavota, Gina & Wiitala, Michael & Metcalf, Robert & Cherubin, Rose, published by Northwestern University Press (2018)
    $39.95
  • Melissus and Eleatic Monism (Cambridge Classical Studies)
    Written by Harriman, Benjamin, published by Cambridge University Press (2019)
    $99.99
  • Hegel and the Spirit: Philosophy as Pneumatology
    Written by Olson, Alan M., published by Princeton University Press (2010)
    $39.95
  • Melissus Between Miletus and Elea (Eleatica) (English and Italian Edition)
    Written by Mansfeld, Jaap, published by Academia Verlag Richarz Gmbh (2016)
    $44.00
 

Cite This Work

APA Style

Costa, D. (2021, March 24). Melissus. World History Encyclopedia. Retrieved from https://www.worldhistory.org/Melissus/

Chicago Style

Costa, Daniel. "Melissus." World History Encyclopedia. Last modified March 24, 2021. https://www.worldhistory.org/Melissus/.

MLA Style

Costa, Daniel. "Melissus." World History Encyclopedia. World History Encyclopedia, 24 Mar 2021. Web. 05 Dec 2021.

Membership